|
Anyone who has followed the recent refugee crisis will notice the
interchangeable use of the terms “migrant” and “refugee” to describe the
people fleeing Syria, Iraq and North Africa, who are attempting to find
safety and a better life in Europe. Depending upon your source of
news, you might also hear the almost belligerent use of phrases and
words like “economic migrant” and “opening the floodgates.”
It was Hannah Arendt who used the term “scum of the earth,”
to describe not the refugees fleeing Nazi control during World War II,
but the treatment they received as they metaphorically washed up on
shores of neighboring countries. She was describing the phenomenon that
transpires when one country or regime has designated some people as
inferior, and how everyone else then views them that way — needy,
dangerous, and likely to cause a run on resources.
In fact, it was this distaste of refugee flows and the problems that arose when other countries, including the United States,
shut their doors on refugees fleeing persecution during World War II
that led to the drafting and ratification of not just the 1951 Convention on the Status of Refugees, but the creation of the United Nations itself. The drafters’ goal set forth in the UN Charter,
“to save succeeding generations from the scourge of war,” were as
mindful of the refugee problem as they were the death and destruction
that accompany interstate conflict. Today, of course, many of our
refugee flows emanate from intrastate conflict, but the problem
remains the same. If it is not safe to remain in your home, where can
you go and who, if anyone, is legally obliged to take you in?
It is worth noting at the outset that the “refugee crisis” in Europe
is not new. As early as the late 1990’s, people were departing Libya in
rickety boats, attempting to make land in Europe. Prior to 2011, they
came primarily from Sudan, Somalia, Eritrea, and occasionally Iraq.
Their objectives, though, were the same — fleeing persecution, fleeing
starvation, fleeing sexual violence, and searching for a better life.
Many of these boats capsized, even in the early days before we began
regularly hearing of it. In the summer of 2008, I was visiting a
refugee center outside of Valletta, Malta when one of the refugees
received a call from a sinking boat. His friend was hanging onto a tuna
net in the middle of the ocean, their boat capsized. We were frantic
to reach the navy or coast guard and ask to send out a boat for them,
but there were no coordinates to give. When we reached the naval
responders they told us that looking for this man would be like hunting
for one grain of sand in the desert.
At least 25,000 people are known
to have died in this manner since 2000. The number is undoubtedly
vastly larger. As early as 1997, Italian naval authorities noted
increasing reports of the foundering and shipwreck of boats departing
from North Africa and Albania. Because in most instances the boats and
the people were long since perished by the time authorities investigated
(when they investigated), these began being referred to as “phantom migrant shipwrecks.”
In the first nine months of 2014 alone, more than 3,000 people
drowned, but now the world’s attention was beginning to focus on the
tragic journey. For a brief time in 2014, several southern European
countries banded together and developed Mare Nostrum, a
“military-humanitarian mission” focused on plotting the course of
refugees (work done by Frontex, the EU external border control agency
established in 2005), and endeavoring to rescue people on foundering
vessels. The operation lasted less than a year before it was ended
through lack of political and economic will to keep it going in the face
of pressure to return refugees, not rescue them and bring them to shore. It is estimated that 300,000 people have attempted the Mediterranean boat crossing in the first nine months of 2015 alone.
Although many or even most of those on the boats are legitimate
refugees, people with a legitimate claim for asylum, those operating the
boats are most certainly the worst sort of smugglers
and human traffickers, profiting from the desperation of their
passengers. These smugglers’ rates depend on their assumptions about
the economic means of refugees based on their countries of origin. A
sub-Saharan African might pay $900, while a Syrian might be charged
$2500; these prices are much reduced from several years ago now that the
“market is saturated.” The fee includes a grueling round of travel
across the southern Libyan Desert, which some say they would rather die
than repeat, before they are delivered to the coast. The boats that
will carry them are packed with 100 — 300 people typically aboard. One
single 100 — 200 mile run from the Libyan coast to Malta or the
southernmost island of Italy might yield a smuggler 90 — 750,000 USD.
Tunisian, Libyan, Italian, Greek, and Maltese fisherman have regularly
encountered foundering boats and, as is required of them under various laws of the sea, many have assisted and brought the passengers to shore. Only to then themselves be arrested for migrant smuggling.
In 2003, the countries of the European Union adopted the Dublin Regulation.
By virtue of this multilateral pact, the European country in which a
potential asylum seeker first set foot had to agree to process his or
her application — anyone seeking asylum in an EU country had to seek it
in the country in which he first landed. This agreement put a
tremendous amount of pressure on countries like Greece, Malta, and
Italy, which initially hosted a large number of asylum seekers, most of
whom wished to seek asylum in the EU, but who were stuck in limbo, many
detained in prison-like camps, hoping to secure an asylum interview or
some processing of an asylum application. It also put a tremendous
strain on the admittedly sporadic ocean search and rescue operations in
effect to try to prevent the multiplying deaths at sea with lack of
clarity even as to whom was responsible for which waters.
A refugee is a person who has a well-founded fear of being persecuted
due to his race, religion, nationality, political opinion, or
membership in a particular social group. People can be formally and
legally identified as refugees, usually by UNHCR or one of their partner
organizations, and if they are lucky, be picked by a country willing to
resettle them. These people arrive in their new host country as formal
refugees, with documents that identify them legally as such, sometimes
even UN passports called laissez-passer
if they are effectively stateless. Under the terms of the host
countries’ domestic legislation, based on recommendations made by UNCHR
and the Refugee Convention, these refugees are often eligible for food,
shelter, medical assistance, education and job training, if it is
available. Presently, 80% of the world’s refugees are hosted in
developing countries. Neither Lebanon nor Jordan are party to the Refugee Convention. Pakistan currently hosts the largest number of refugees (1.6 million).
Those who arrive at the border of a potential host country without
the refugee designation are considered asylum seekers. Presently,
Germany, Sweden, and France host the top number of asylum seekers,
followed by the UK, Italy, Belgium, Hungary, Austria, the Netherlands,
and Poland. The burden is on the asylum applicant to prove he has a
well-founded fear of persecution due to one of the five categories.
Those whose primary motivation is deemed to be “improving their lives”
or the lives of their children are considered “economic migrants,”
not entitled to asylum or the refugee designation. It is almost as if
by electing not to remain in a developing or already overwhelmed
potential host country, a refugee is presumed to be an economic migrant,
unless he can prove otherwise.
This is why you so often hear the Syrians fleeing to Europe referred
to as “migrants.” The implication is that they are not refugees because
their primary motivation is not fleeing persecution, but rather seeking
a better life. This is also why you hear people saying, “they could
have stayed in the refugee camps in Turkey or Lebanon or Jordan; they
just didn’t want to.” These people are arguing that they were “safe”
from persecution when they hit the first host country; they only left
those camps because they did not like them.
In order to examine this argument, it is important to understand the
conditions for refugees in those camps, in most camps, really, most of
which are not even “camps,” but actually people trying to find safety in
urban settings, particularly those Syrians in Lebanon. To put these host countries in context consider the following: first, Turkey
currently hosts almost 2 million refugees, Lebanon hosts over 1
million, and Jordan has more than 600,000. These three countries
already hosted Iraqi refugees before the conflict in Syria even began.
Now Iraq hosts 250,000 Syrian refugees. Secondly, at the time the
conflict began, Syria also hosted thousands of Iraqi and Palestinian
refugees and these people have also been displaced by the conflict. At a
minimum, we can see that these “camps” are overcrowded, unsanitary, unsafe, and unwelcoming. They are riddled with human traffickers, child labor,
organized crime networks, and others who would exploit the most
displaced and vulnerable. Many refugees are unable to work, go to
school, or have any real hope of a life for themselves or their
children. Many state that their primary concern is lack of food.
This is why so many Syrians and Iraqis are seeking to enter Europe,
first through North African routes, and more recently overland (or after
reaching Albania) through Serbia and Hungary. Other factors are also
in play. In 2012, Israel completed its border fence on its border with
Egypt. Eritreans and Somalis who had previously been able to attempt
to flee heading east, now turned west, adding to the flow of people
attempting to depart North Africa by boat, headed for Europe. UNHCR
reported the forced displacement of almost 6 million in the first six
months of 2013 alone, about half Afghans, Somalis, and Syrians
attempting to escape violence and “extraordinary hardship.” In August
2013, UNHCR estimated
that there were 110,000 Syrian refugees in Libya in 2013. By September
2013, the estimate was 250–300,000 Syrians in Egypt, and Egypt was forcibly returning
them to Syria, Lebanon, Gaza and Turkey. Pressure points have been
building for some time. By 2013, Europe hosted 79% of the total number
of asylum seekers in the world, with the US and Canada together
accounting for 16%.
Under the UNCHR guidelines, there are three “durable solutions” for
refugees: resettlement, repatriation and local integration. Given the
saturation point in Jordan, Lebanon and Turkey, refugees are effectively
or legally unable to integrate locally. This leaves two solutions —
returning home (not an option) or resettlement to a third country.
Unless or until a third country identifies a refugee and agrees to take
him, resettlement is only a hypothetical. Unless the refugee can get to
that country himself, apply for asylum, and obtain his refugee
designation. This is why Syrians are now flooding into Europe.
The country claiming to take the largest share of refugees annually
is the United States. There are a few problems with this claim. First,
the cap set by Congress is the number typically cited. Not cited is
the number that actually arrive.
Secondly, several other countries take a much larger share per capita.
Third, when a country publicly agrees to accept one refugee flow,
operations often begin behind the scenes to “hurry along and deport”
asylum seekers already in the country who are perceived to have less
“grantable” claims. One of the goals of the Refugee Convention is to
share the responsibility of meeting the needs of refugees among host
countries. By 2014, UNHCR estimated more than 50 million refugees
worldwide. Countries that might be expected to absorb some Syrian
refugees, like Saudi Arabia, UAE, Kuwait, and Qatar, have taken none.
While they have been silent as to why this is so, speculation centers on
the fears of the leadership of these countries that the relatively
well-educated and cosmopolitan Syrians would shake up the status quo too
much for the these nations. The total number of refugees that
accepting countries agree to take is less than 1%
of the total number of refugees in the world. The total number that
countries agree to take is often not a real number. For a variety of
reasons (national security concerns, inefficiency, too long of a waiting
time) countries routinely take far fewer than the total number they
claim to be willing to accept. The United States, for instance,
regularly falls short of its cap (typically set at between 50–70
thousand per year), sometimes by as many as 20–25,000 people.
One new problem with the conflation of refugees fleeing intrastate
conflict and the “war on terror” is that we are looking at millions of
effectively stateless people. In a country like Syria where fear of
Assad has now shifted to fear of ISIS, speculation about whether a
Syrian refugee might have provided material support to a terrorist group
rises, and the likelihood that any will be safe to return home
decreases. The more politicians speculate about the likelihood of
Syrian refugees being terrorists or their supporters, the less likely it
becomes that any country will accept them. There is no evidentiary
requirement that a government prove why it thinks a particular person
might be a terrorist sympathizer and therein not refugee material. A
mere unfounded suspicion is sufficient. When one country speculates
about a particular individual, no one will take that individual
thereafter. The speculation and fear itself renders a large group of
people effectively stateless. One need only remember the Uighurs held in Guantanamo by the United States to understand this dynamic.
It is worth noting a few more things: the refugees flooding into
Europe now are not all Syrian, although the tragic plight of Syrians
fleeing their decimated country provides the face for the current
crisis. Furthermore, the United States has been faced with a similar
crisis over the past few years. In the summer of 2014, the story of the
thousands of women
and children fleeing extreme violence in Central America and being
detained on arrival in the United States was regularly in the news
cycle. These women and children have not gone anywhere (except for
those who have been deported), nor have they stopped fleeing, or been
granted asylum, yet their “crisis” has been overtaken even in US news
outlets by the one in Europe. These women and children,
too, are being denied asylum and deported, cast as “migrants,” not
refugees. The violence they are fleeing, they are told, does not fit
under any of the five categories — a contestable claim, as many similar
asylum cases have been won arguing that the targeting by gangs who
cannot be controlled by their home government constitutes a particular
social group.
The current “crisis” is a crisis because sovereign nations fear that
the floodgates will open, that they will be unable to control their
borders, that each refugee will cost
the host government (an estimated $14,000 in the short term, to be
precise, although a long term economic boon), or, inevitably, that they
might be a security risk. The fact remains, though, that these were
the same fears articulated during World War II, and yet we still came
together to form the United Nations and ratify the Refugee Convention in
order to prevent the scourge of future refugees flows depleting the
resources of a few countries. And, it bears remembering, because we
knew it was the right thing to do and we felt shame for having done it
so badly.
The UN High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR) is mandated by the
United Nations to lead and coordinate international action for the
worldwide protection of refugees and the resolution of refugee problems.
Its primary purpose is to safeguard the rights and well-being of
refugees, including by working with states to ensure everyone can access
asylum, seek third country resettlement, or return voluntarily to their
home state (the three “durable solutions”). UNHCR is also charged with
enforcing (or encouraging; they have no enforcement authority) the
principle of non-refoulement, whereby states are prohibited from forcing back or returning anyone who fears persecution in the home state. Non-Refoulement is jus cogens,
binding even states not party to the Refugee Convention. The
organization is donor funded, and its largest donors have consistently
been member states of Western Europe and the European Union itself,
along with Japan and the United States. Like most UN agencies, UNHCR is
only permitted to operate in a country where it has permission from the
host state. Thus, it begins a fine dance of attempting to lobby the
state hosting a refugee population to do so according to the
requirements of the Refugee Convention, without losing its mandate to
operate in that state by acting too forcefully. UNHCR is currently
operating in Libya “cautiously,” as it has no formal memo of
understanding. Libya remains the transit sending state for most of the
migrants heading to Europe through North Africa. The operating costs
for UNHCR in Libya for 2012 alone amount to more than 31 million USD, although only 12.7 million USD was actually available.
At present, European countries are struggling to come to an agreement
with one another on the share of refugees each will take. At the same
time, anticipating they will take some, several are ridding themselves
of lingering asylum seekers from other parts of the world to make way.
More than half a million migrants have arrived in Germany
this year, for example. Only about half of those who have already
applied for asylum are from Syria or Iraq. The rest are from struggling
European countries like Albania and Kosovo. Europe is changing its
laws to try to stem the flow of so-called “economic migrants.” As of
August, anyone who makes what is deemed to be a “baseless” or
“frivolous” asylum claim can be barred from re-entering any of the
European Union’s passport-free Schengen area,
for up to five years. Germany and several other countries have also
begun instituting random passport and document checks within the
Schengen area, effectively altering the notion of the EU as a free
travel zone. Six EU member states are outside of the Schengen zone
(Bulgaria, Croatia, Cyprus, Ireland, Romania, and the UK) and three
non-EU states are within the Schengen zone (Norway, Iceland, and
Switzerland). Bulgaria, Croatia, Cyprus, and Romania have undertaken
an obligation to enter the Schengen zone as part of their EU member
status. Schengen states are only permitted to institute passport checks
as a temporary measure and this has begun in earnest. Since last year,
Austria, a country firmly within the Schengen open border zone, has
stopped and denied entry to at least 2100 non-EU “foreigners” transiting
from Italy.
The problem with “getting rid of” some applicants to make way for
others is that many assumptions are then made about the viability of an
asylum claim based not on individual circumstances, but on one’s country
of origin. A presumption is set against those from Kosovo or Serbia,
for example, and (potentially) favors someone from Syria. This is not
the way the Refugee Convention is designed to operate. The notion of
the Refugee Convention is that anyone with a well-founded,
credible fear should be able to make that claim, obliging local
authorities to protect anyone successful in doing so.
Hungary has erected a fence on its border with Serbia. Bulgaria is
planning a fence on its border with Turkey and Greece has already
erected one. Meanwhile, the current US presidential candidates are
outdoing one another with the length and strength of their proposed
border fences. Malta and Italy have attempted to push back people
trying to land on their coasts, even when they were aboard ships that
had rescued them after theirs sank. This should call to mind shiploads
of Jewish European children and refugees attempting to land in the
United States during World War II and being denied entry. Or the shiploads of Europeans attempting to flee violence in Europe during World War II by fleeing to North Africa.
When we take the long view, it becomes easier to see why aiding
refugees now is important for all of our sakes and all of our safety.
When we operate out of fear, we are taking the short view.
Presently, we are operating out of fear. Certainly the refugees
fleeing persecution and the migrants seeking a better life are, but
also, and maybe most importantly, the nation-states into which these
refugees and migrants hope to make their way are also. Instead of
operating out of fear, we need to honor the agreements we committed to
in creating the United Nations and ratifying the Refugee Convention.
We need to remember the spirit in which we committed to these
principles, and then we need to carry out these principles and protect
refugees.
Dina Francesca Haynes
A recent op-ed in the New York Times with the provocative title “Stop Universities
from Hoarding Money” once again raises the issue of university endowments. It focuses in large part
on the extraordinary amounts elite universities either “hoard” or spend on fees
to investment advisors and hedge funds in contrast to the much smaller sums
spent on “tuition assistance, fellowships and prizes,” those things seen as the
university’s true mission. The author,
a tax professor, suggests that universities with endowments in excess of $100
million should be required to expend at least eight percent of their endowments
each year. This is not a new proposal; similar proposals arise periodically. Of course entities with such large sums
(Harvard’s endowment is reported to exceed $32.5 billion) are formidable players in politics so these calls
generally go unheeded.
To understand why we all have an interest in these matters one
must know a thing or two about federal tax law as it applies to charitable
organizations. Universities are classified as “public charities” which status means
that they can generally earn and accumulate money exempt from federal income
tax. Policy experts sometimes refer to these benefits as a taxpayer “ subsidy,”
to the university, because exempting the university from tax is the same as
taxing it like other entities and then returning to it its tax payments rather
than using them for other public benefit. Imagine the potential tax liability of
an institution like Harvard if its receipts (tuition, income and gains on
investments) were subject to the income tax. That figure would reach at least
tens of millions of dollars annually. The idea behind the tax exemption, of
course, is that it allows universities to provide more research, knowledge and
education—all seen as public goods. And tax-exemption is not the only federal
tax subsidy from which universities benefit. Donors’ taxes are reduced when
they make contributions to universities through generous tax deductions. Like
exempting universities from the income tax, subsidizing donations to those
institutions with taxpayer dollars increases the availability of the public
goods produced by universities.
By implementing the foregoing tax benefits, Congress apparently
assumed that we (the taxpayers) are getting what we pay for. But is that true
as respects university endowments? Why does Harvard have $32.5 billion and what
is it doing with all that money? Why did Yale pay $480 million to private equity fund managers compared with $170 million for tuition assistance, fellowships and prizes? Should these wealthy elite universities
be spending more of their endowments on their core mission? That question has
been considered by a couple of scholars. Unfortunately, the results seem to
suggest that when it comes to at least some university endowments, we are not,
in fact, getting what we pay for.
It seems to be generally accepted that a university should
spend no more of its endowment than the endowment generates in income and
(perhaps) capital appreciation. Many spend income only and allow capital
appreciation to accrue, which will generally allow an endowment to grow much
larger over time. These practices are justified on the basis of
“intergenerational equity.” Maintaining the endowment’s value over time means
that it can continue to support the university’s activities indefinitely. But a
1990 study
found that the basis for the intergenerational equity argument had little merit.
And the fact remains that elite university endowments are growing at
substantial rates.
A more recent study, undertaken in 2010 sought to determine why universities, in the immediate
aftermath of the 2008 financial crisis, slashed operating budgets, laid off
employees, froze salaries, and delayed expansion projects, among other things,
rather than dipping into multibillion dollar endowments. Reasons given by the
universities were that pre-crisis spending was unsustainable, the endowments
were legally restricted as to use, and that the investments were generally
illiquid and difficult to access. This study found each of these reasons to be
unpersuasive. The author concluded that the endowments served primarily as
status symbols, and that universities would reach for any other source of
funding to avoid diminishing their endowments.
There is certainly precedent for requiring tax-exempt
organizations to expend a minimum percentage of their assets. Private foundations are different from public charities in that rather than being
supported by a wide range of public contributions they might be funded only by
one family or even one individual. Because private foundations are not
“publicly-supported” federal tax statutes require them to expend at least five
percent of their net investment assets on charitable endeavors each year.
Failure to comply subjects them to a potentially crippling penalty tax. Under the same principle, universities should be using their tax-subsidized
endowments to support their core charitable missions. Those who don’t should be
penalized.
On Monday, August 31, Gregory Hobbs will step down as Associate
Justice of the Colorado Supreme Court, a position he has held for the
past nineteen years. I was extremely fortunate to serve as a law clerk
for Justice Hobbs for the 2000–2001 term. On the occasion of his
retirement from the bench, I wanted to add my voice to the chorus of
praise for this extraordinary public servant.
Justice Hobbs was (is!) a water law expert, a historian, a poet, a
keen cultural observer, and a man with his finger on the pulse of the
communities he served. More than once during my clerkship, he reminded
me that the Court’s authority came with profound responsibility: each
decision directly affected lives and livelihoods. There was no place
for judicial (or judicial clerk) egotism or haughtiness. At a time when
the news cycle and daytime television converged to create a culture
celebrating sassy, snarky judges, Justice Hobbs was always a jurist of
remarkable care and humility.
But a commitment to judicial humility still left plenty of room for
the Justice to make his individual mark. “There is a second story in
the footnotes,” he once said to me during my clerkship. He was talking
about his majority opinion in Board of County Commissioners v. Vail Associates, Inc.,
an opus of an opinion that concerned a head-spinning series of
exemptions to the general rule allowing counties to impose property
taxes. The opinion was a careful parsing of case law and statutory and
constitutional text, but it was also a fascinating jaunt into Colorado’s
history. There was a second story in the footnotes, taking
readers on a ride from 1877 to the turn of the twenty-first century, and
folding in references to mining, farming, ranching, and skiing—the
things that make Colorado uniquely Colorado.
I think of that opinion whenever I think of Justice Hobbs, because he
too is uniquely Colorado, and because his influence on me and my career
can, in a sense, be found in the footnotes as well. Well after my
clerkship ended, I have come to regard him as a mentor and an example.
It comes in the way he conducts himself as a father, grandfather,
husband, friend, boss, and jurist. It comes in the humility he has
always shown for his judicial position, and the constant recognition
that doing what is right by the law is not always easy. It comes in his
love of the State of Colorado, its people, and its institutions. It
comes in his ability to stand by his principles while remaining willing
to reevaluate his positions. It is a rare judge—indeed, a rare
person—who can approach his job with such pleasure, dignity and candor
day in and day out. The interaction between Justice Hobbs and his
clerks, and among the Justices themselves, gave me a deep appreciation
for how appellate decisionmaking should work. Those moments
still influence me as a law professor today: I spend most of my time
teaching, thinking, and writing about how judges decide cases and how
judicial behavior influences others in the legal system.
So the text of my time clerking may read, “Law Clerk, Hon. Gregory J.
Hobbs, Jr., Colorado Supreme Court, 2000–2001,” but the real story is
in the footnotes. The people of Colorado have been blessed to have
Justice Hobbs on the Court for almost 20 years. I have been blessed to
know him for nearly fifteen years, where his example has been a constant
influence. Thank you, GJH.
Jordan M. Singer
In an opinion piece for the New York Times, Professor William Baude suggested that, following the Supreme Court’s decision in Obergefell v. Hodges
striking down prohibitions on same-sex marriage, the door may well be
open to the argument that bans on plural marriage should fall as well.
Baude takes as his cue the suggestion in the dissent of Chief Justice
John Roberts that “[o]ne immediate question invited by the [ Obergefell] majority’s position is whether States may retain the definition of marriage as a union of two people.”
The answer is, of course, “yes.” Explaining why, though, may take some doing. As my colleague, Jordan Singer, has noted, the decision in Obergefell was, at a minimum, “ befuddling.”
One reason is because its author, Justice Anthony Kennedy, eschewed a
traditional equal protection analysis for the kind of soaring rhetoric
that has become a hallmark of his opinions in the area of individual
rights. Though the respect he accords the subject matter is notable, at
the end of the day, lower courts, state government officials and lawyers
need a good deal more to be able to understand the limits of our
constitutional commitment to equality.
Had Kennedy embraced a traditional equal protection analysis—as did the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court in Goodridge v. Department of Public Health,
the first decision to overturn a same-sex marriage ban—the force of the
Chief Justice’s predictions about plural marriage likely would have
been blunted. To understand why, we must remember that, despite the fact
that it is fundamental, unlike nearly all other individual
constitutional rights—both explicit and implicit—the right to marry does
not exist unless the state provides for it. In other words, the
Constitution does not compel states to offer their citizens the
opportunity to enter into the legal relationship known as marriage. But
if a state chooses to offer its citizens that opportunity, it cannot
discriminate against parties who seek to enter into marriage absent some
legitimate basis for doing so.
As numerous federal and state courts have concluded, there is no
legitimate basis for excluding same-sex couples from marriage. Though as
a historical matter such couples were not eligible for marriage, that
is not a valid argument for continuing to prohibit them from marrying
when they otherwise satisfy the structural requirements for eligibility.
Those requirements contemplate two parties who have consented to be
married in the eyes of the law, so that they may both enjoy the
particular benefits that this binary legal relationship provides and
undertake the particular responsibilities it assigns. Nothing about the
inherent nature of those benefits and responsibilities disables same-sex
couples from entering into marriage.
The point here is that every state has limited marriage to a union of
two—and only two—parties. That binary relationship forms the structural
core of the institution of marriage. For a court to hold same-sex
couples equally eligible to enter into that relationship no more changed
the definition of marriage than would an order foreclosing a state from
declining to provide a particular opportunity to otherwise qualified
members of the opposite sex. See United States v. Virginia. On the other hand, for a court to order that a state must extend the opportunity to enter into marriage to any
combination of parties who desire it would take that court well beyond
the judicial role contemplated by current equal protection doctrine.
To illustrate, consider this hypothetical situation: suppose in response to Obergefell
the state of Pennsyltucky decided to get out of the marriage business
altogether—in other words, suppose the state decided not to offer its
citizens the opportunity to enter into any form of civil marriage. Could
a court order the state to create that legal relationship,
with all of the public and administrative costs associated with managing
it? No more than a court could order a state to provide funds to allow
aspiring but impoverished political candidates to run for office. It’s
equally unlikely a court would order a state that currently offers its
citizens the opportunity to enter into binary marriage—which is to say,
every state under current law—to admit any number of parties to that
relationship. Unlike the relief requested by the plaintiffs in Obergefell, such an order would in fact change the structural definition of marriage.
At bottom, multiple-party relationships simply aren’t the same as
two-party relationships. The binary relationship—and not the genders of
the parties to it—lies at the heart of marriage as the states have
defined it today. Plural marriage may come, but it will be the result of
legislative rather than judicial action.
Lawrence Friedman
One of the more politically opportune reactions to the final week of the Supreme Court Term came from Senator Ted Cruz. His proposal:
a Constitutional amendment that would replace life tenure for the
Supreme Court with periodic retention elections. Under the Cruz plan,
each Justice would face the voters in the second national election after
initial confirmation, and every eight years thereafter. Justices would
need a simple majority of “retain” votes to stay on the bench.
Justices who are not retained would be replaced and would not be
eligible for reappointment.
The Senator couched his proposal
as a response to “a long line of judicial assaults on our Constitution
and the common-sense values that have made America great.” Offering
some red meat for his conservative base, he added that retention
elections would provide a remedy for “the decisions that have deformed
our constitutional order and have debased our culture” by “giving the
people the regular, periodic power to pass judgment on the judgments of
their judges.”
As a tool of partisan accountability, the proposal shouldn’t work.
Retention elections have been used at the state level for 75 years, and
only in very rare instances—California in 1986, Iowa in 2010—have
multiple justices on a single court lost retention elections in the wake
of a politically controversial ruling. Citizen anger over controversial
decisions generally does not translate into judges being kicked off the
bench. Put another way, retention voters are assessing something more
than mere case outcomes when determining whether to keep a judge in
office.
This may seem surprising, given that politicians routinely try to
rally their bases in reaction to Supreme Court decisions they disfavor.
(Consider the left’s reaction to Citizens United or Heller, or the right’s reaction to Sebelius or Obergefell.) But ordinary voters don’t think like politicians. As I have documented here and here,
to everyday citizens, a judge’s perceived commitment to a fair legal
process is far more important than specific case outcomes. Voters will
forgive a judge with whose rulings they disagree as long as those
rulings appear to have been reached fairly and with respect for the
court’s (often circumscribed) institutional role. Voters are less
forgiving, however, when a judge appears to have intruded into the
domain of the legislature, acted obnoxiously, or reached a decision that
lacks a solid legal grounding.
Senator Cruz is a smart man, and he must know that voters assess
judges differently than they do legislators or executives. So I doubt
he is using retention merely as a conduit for channeling partisan anger.
Quite the opposite: he appears to be counting on voters to
assess the Justices on their commitment to procedural fairness and
institutional humility, and to find that commitment lacking.
Unfortunately, in this regard the Supreme Court has not helped its own cause. The series of befuddling opinions in Obergefell v. Hodges
nicely illustrates the problem. Justice Kennedy’s majority opinion on
same-sex marriage was laden with soaring, poetic rhetoric about the
profundity of marriage and the entitlement of all people to “equal
dignity in the eyes of the law.” One is apt to agree with these
sentiments as a matter of policy or even morality. But a constitutional
exegesis demands something more. The Obergefell majority
never cleanly and clearly explained why it was the province of the
Supreme Court to accomplish what Congress and state legislatures might
have (eventually) done themselves. Indeed, Obergefell was
arguably far less grounded in the constitutional text than either of the
equivalent efforts on same-sex marriage offered by the Iowa Supreme Court and Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court
years earlier. In doing so, the majority opened the door to criticisms
that the Court had overstepped its institutional bounds.
The dissenting opinions subsequently pulled that door right off its
hinges. The Chief Justice lamented, “The majority’s decision is an act
of will, not legal judgment…. Just who do we think we are?” He went on:
“Five lawyers have closed the debate and enacted their own view of
marriage as a matter of constitutional law.” Justice Scalia went
further, charging that the majority opinion “lack[ed] even a thin veneer
of law” and ruling a “system of government that makes the People
subordinate to a committee of nine unelected lawyers.” Justice Alito
picked up the same theme, warning that the Constitution forbids “five
unelected Justices from imposing their personal vision of liberty upon
the American people.” Only Justice Thomas constrained his dissenting
opinion to a legalist discussion about constitutional meaning.
As a debate over national policy or constitutional philosophy, the five Obergefell
opinions make fascinating and important reading. As a vehicle for
increasing, or even sustaining, the institutional legitimacy of the
court, however, they are collectively a train wreck. Anyone who reads
the majority opinion and suspects the court of moderately overstepping
its institutional role will, upon reading the dissents, find a far more
grievous critique. The Court, we are told, undermined the core of
American democracy through unelected lawyers and (in Justice Scalia’s
inimitable words) “judicial Putsch.” Even if one agrees with the
outcome of the case (and I count myself among them), the internecine
squabbling over institutional overreach is deeply unsettling. The
majority could have worked harder to formulate an opinion that sounded
less like public policy, and the dissenters could have made their points
with far more responsible rhetorical flourish. No wonder Senator Cruz
felt that the public might be ready for retention elections.
Thanks to the court’s self-flagellation, the Cruz proposal cannot be
treated as mere pandering to his right-leaning base. Public respect for
the judiciary is near a 15-year low,
and allegations by the Justices that their own colleagues do not
respect the rule of law cannot help. Those who want to see the Court
regain its lost institutional legitimacy can only hope that the Justices
recognize the damage that comes from their public dysfunction, and
collectively work to repair it.
Jordan M. Singer
“The issue in this case is whether the Act’s [the Affordable
Care Act] tax credits are available in States that have a Federal
Exchange rather than a State Exchange.” King v. Burwell, 576 U.S. __ (2015)
(p. 5). The Affordable Care Act (ACA) requires each state to create its
own health insurance Exchange, however, if a state refuses to do so,
then the Secretary of Health and Human Services (HHS) is authorized to
“establish and operate such Exchange within the State.” Sec.
18041(c)(1).” (p. 5). Only sixteen States and the District of Columbia
created their own Exchanges, while thirty-four States utilize the
federal Exchange administered by the Department of Health and Human
Services. (p. 6).
The tax credits, which are authorized by IRC sec. 36B, are allowed to
“applicable taxpayers” who obtain health insurance through “an Exchange
established by the State under section 1311 of the Patient Protection
and Affordable Care act….” (p. 5). The IRS addressed the availability of
tax credits to individuals acquiring health insurance through an HHS
Exchange by adopting the definition of “Exchange” as used in an HHS
regulation, 45 CFR sec. 155.20, which provided that taxpayers are
eligible for a tax credit if they are enrolled in an Exchange which
serves the individual market, “regardless of whether the Exchange is
established and operated by a State… or by HHS….” (p. 6).
In prior proceedings, the U.S. District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia granted the Defendants’ Motion to Dismiss, 997 F.Supp.2d 415 (2014), and the District Court judgment was affirmed by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the 4th Circuit, 759 F.3d 358 (2014).
Justice Roberts, who was joined by Justices Kennedy, Ginsberg,
Breyer, Sotomayor, and Kagan, wrote the majority opinion, and held that
tax credits for health insurance under IRC sec. 36B applied to
individuals acquiring coverage on federal health insurance exchanges
under the Affordable Care Act (ACA), even though sec. 36B states that
the credits apply to insurance plans that are enrolled in through “an
Exchange established by the State under [42 U.S.C. sec. 18031].” Justice
Roberts’ reasoning was based on the ambiguity reflected in sec. 36B
when it was interpreted in connection with other provisions of the ACA,
and the manner in which those ambiguities were either consistent or
inconsistent with Congress’ intent that the ACA expand health care
coverage, and lower the cost of health insurance as a means of
facilitating that expansion of coverage. The Congressional intent to
expand health insurance coverage through the ACA would have been
undermined if the sec. 36B tax credits were not applicable to
individuals enrolled in health insurance plans through the federal
exchanges.
Justice Roberts discussed the history of health reform in the United
States and how states which instituted guaranteed issue, which required
insurers to cover persons regardless of health status, and community
rating, which restricted insurers from taking health status into account
in setting premiums, ultimately led to “adverse selection,” which
occurred when a person would only seek insurance once they became sick
or in need of health care coverage. Because insurers were required to
cover persons regardless of health status and could not take health
status into account in setting premiums for specific insureds, they were
forced to raise rates for all insureds in order to account for the
higher health costs, increasing the cost of coverage and reducing the
numbers of individuals who could afford coverage. Justice Roberts wrote
that “This led to an economic “death spiral.” As premiums rose higher
and higher, and the number of people buying insurance sank lower and
lower, insurers began to leave the market entirely.” (p. 2).
Congress, relying on the Massachusetts health reform effort in 2006,
included in the ACA a guaranteed issue and community rating component,
but also included an individual mandate requiring most individuals to
maintain health insurance coverage (either employer-provided, private
coverage, or government-subsidized coverage), or pay a penalty. For
individuals whose household income is between 100% and 400% of the
federal poverty level income amount, they are eligible for a tax credit
pursuant to IRC sec. 36B. The tax credit lowers the cost of health
insurance for working class and middle class taxpayers, while the
mandate brings into the health insurance pool more young and healthy
persons (who would otherwise not obtain coverage) whose premiums
subsidize the cost of coverage for sick and older persons under the ACA.
( p.4).
Justice Roberts, in discussing Congress’ awareness of the necessity
of the individual mandate and the tax credit to the reform effort,
writes: “These three reforms are closely intertwined. As noted, Congress
found that the guaranteed issue and community rating requirements would
not work without the coverage requirement. Sec. 18091(2)(I). And the
coverage requirement would not work without the tax credits. “The reason
is that, without the tax credits, the cost of buying insurance would
exceed eight percent of income for a large number of individuals, which
would exempt them from the coverage requirement. Given the relationship
between these three reforms, the Act provided that they should take
effect on the same day—January 1, 2014….” (p. 5).
Justice Roberts determined that due to the “economic and political
significance” of the tax credits and their central role in the statutory
scheme Congress created under the ACA, “It is especially unlikely that
Congress would have delegated” to the IRS the authority to resolve any
ambiguities with the tax credit under its regulatory authority without
expressly doing so. He concludes that it is the Court’s, and not the
IRS’s duty to determine the correct interpretation of sec. 36B. (p 8).
Justice Roberts’ analysis first finds that the authority granted to
the Secretary of HHS to “establish and operate such Exchange within the
State,” pursuant to sec. 18041(c)(1) of the ACA, shows that the HHS
exchanges and the state Exchanges under sec. 18031 “are equivalent” by
virtue of HHS establishing “such Exchange” under 18041, or, that HHS is
to establish “the same Exchange that the State was directed to establish
under Section 18031.” (p. 9–10).
Justice Roberts then analyzes sec. 36B in context with other
provisions of the ACA (sec. 18032 defining “qualified individual” and
sec. 300gg-91(d)(21) defining “Exchange”) and determines that a federal
Exchange may be considered as one “established by the State” in order
for the federal Exchange to function consistently with those other
provisions within the statutory scheme of the ACA, resulting in
ambiguity in the interpretation of sec. 36B within the context of the
ACA’s statutory scheme, as compared to a literal interpretation of
“established by the State” under sec. 36B. (p. 10–13).
Applying the principle of statutory interpretation that “the words of
a statute must be read in their context with a view to their place in
the overall statutory scheme,” Justice Roberts concludes that a strict
interpretation of sec. 36B must be rejected because “it would
destabilize the individual insurance market in any State with a Federal
Exchange, and likely create the very ‘death spirals’ that Congress
designed the Act to avoid.” (p. 9, 15).
Justice Roberts holds that the sec. 36B tax credits are allowed for
health insurance purchased on “any Exchange created under the Act.”
Justice Scalia wrote the dissenting opinion and was joined by
Justices Thomas and Alito. Justice Scalia applies a literal
interpretation of sec. 36B and concludes that the tax credits only apply
to Exchanges established by the States, therefore, no tax credits are
allowed for health insurance purchased on a federal Exchange. (p. 2).
In contrast to Justice Roberts’ broad-based ambiguity analysis, which
relies on his interpretation of sec. 36B in the context of the purpose
and design of the ACA and his conclusion that a literal interpretation
of the statute would conflict with the ACA’s design and purpose, Justice
Scalia focuses solely on the language of the statute itself in
determining whether there is any ambiguity, and finding no ambiguity in
the statutory language, concludes that there is no reason to consider
the ACA’s purpose and design for the purpose of interpreting sec. 36B.
(p. 13).
Justice Scalia suggests that the design of the ACA was intended to
incentivize states to create and operate their own exchanges and that
limiting the 36B tax credits to health insurance plans purchased on a
state exchange was one means of encouraging states to create their own
exchanges. (p. 15-16). In light of that suggestion, he finds that
interpreting sec. 36B to allow tax credits for health insurance
purchased on a federal Exchange eliminates any need on the part of the
state to create its own Exchange since the tax credit will be available
on a federal Exchange. (p. 16).
Justice Scalia also states that the majority, rather than
interpreting sec. 36B is actually rewriting the statute, which is a duty
belonging to Congress.
Discussion
This case, at its most basic level, is a statutory interpretation
dispute. The lower courts which decided this case came to the same
judgment as the Supreme Court, but each with slightly different
reasoning.
Justice Roberts’ opinion applies a broad and policy-based analysis of
both the legislative intent and design of the ACA in order to determine
not only how the health insurance Exchanges were intended to operate,
but also as a means of determining which interpretation of sec. 36B was
most consistent with Congress’ purpose and design for the ACA.
Justice Scalia applied a more limited analysis, focusing solely on
the statutory language of sec. 36B, and finding no ambiguity in the
statute itself, determined that there was no need to analyze the purpose
and the design of the ACA in interpreting the statutory language.
Justice Scalia’s criticism that the Court is rewriting the statute,
not interpreting it, is very interesting. I think that your conclusion
as to whether the Court is interpreting sec. 36B, or rewriting it,
depends upon whether you agree with Justice Roberts’ or Justice Scalia’s
approach in determining and analyzing statutory ambiguity. In light of
the complex design and interlocking provisions of the ACA, and the need
to analyze sec. 36B in the context of those aspects of the law in order
to fully comprehend how it fit within the statutory scheme, Justice
Roberts, as well as the lower courts, decided the case correctly.
Wilton B. Hyman
On June 26 the U.S. Supreme Court decided the “same-sex marriage” case Obergefell v. Hodges.
The Court held unconstitutional, by a 5-4 vote, state laws that limit
marriage to heterosexual couples. According to the Court, these limits
violate both the Due Process and Equal Protection clauses of the 14th
Amendment.
Justice Kennedy’s opinion for the Court focuses on the crucial role
that marriage, as a component of the liberty protected by the Due
Process clause, plays both in individuals’ lives and in structuring
society. Denying same sex-couples the opportunity to marry not only
affects what type of society we live in, but also impoverishes the lives
of a particular group of people in society. According to the Court,
individuals define themselves through marriage. In addition, through
marriage they access other “freedoms, such as expression, intimacy, and
spirituality.” (p. 13) Marriage is also a means for individuals to
achieve the “highest ideals of love, fidelity, devotion, sacrifice, and
family.” (p. 28) Furthermore, children in same-sex families are injured
by having to endure the stigma of familial inferiority as a result of
the non-recognition of their parents’ marriages. (p. 15)
Each of the four dissents objects to the majority’s conclusion that
there is a violation of the Due Process clause. The dissenting justices
argue that Justice Kennedy’s reasons for finding that same-sex couples
have a protected fundamental right to marry are matters of policy and
that the state legislatures, not the U.S. Supreme Court, should decide
what policies are best for the people and society overall. The Chief
Justice’s dissent, for example, does not deny that there is a
fundamental right to marry; instead the Chief Justice argues that this
fundamental right applies only to heterosexual couples because “the core
definition of marriage … [is]the union of a man and a woman.” (pp. 8
and 16.) This “core” meaning of the fundamental right of marriage is
“deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.” Constraints on
the definition of constitutionally protected rights keep the courts from
legislating.
The majority and the dissents all recognize that the terms “liberty”
and “marriage” must be interpreted. Unconstrained interpretation is
problematic because it is difficult to distinguish from the act of
legislating. Nonetheless, courts must interpret the words of a text,
including a constitution. To be legitimate within our system, judicial
interpretations must be bounded by an accepted and acceptable structure.
The Court and the dissents disagree on what this structure is.
The Chief Justice’s dissent searches for a “core” meaning of marriage
as a means of avoiding excessive interpretation. However, as the
Court notes, the institution of marriage has changed dramatically over
time. Different “core” meanings can be identified at different moments
in time, space, and society. As Justice Kennedy wrote in his opinion
for the Court, the doctrine of coverture was critical to the meaning of
marriage in the early 19th century. At the time, a married woman’s
husband could have determined where she would live, whether she could
enter any particular contract, and how to employ any assets she may have
owned upon marriage. He could also decide whether to force sexual
relations on her and under what circumstances to discipline her
physically or otherwise. In short, the central feature of her marriage
might have been her subordination to her husband, not the fact that he
was sexually male. The Chief Justice’s definition of marriage as based
on heterosexuality is a choice among many central definitions of
marriage.
The Court’s definition of marriage relies on a different set of
concepts to constrain its interpretation: individual autonomy, intimacy
and expression; the fundamental role that marriage plays in promoting
child development and in structuring society; and the importance of
equality as also articulated in the 14th Amendment.
For many decades, equality has had a critical function in identifying
the proper role for courts in interpreting the constitutionality of
majoritarian legislation. In our democratic system the courts protect
minorities from oppression by the majority. (p. 24) See United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938)
As the Court’s opinion notes, the ideas behind the Equal Protection
clause reinforce the liberties protected by Due Process; restricting
marriage to heterosexuals would have the effect of “diminish[ing] the
personhood” of members of same-sex couples. (p. 19) Similarly, in U.S. v. Windsor,
the Court highlighted the humiliation and financial harm to children in
same-sex families when their parents’ marriages are not recognized by
the federal government. This role of protecting minorities against harm
done by the majority has been central to the role of the Court.
Since they cannot avoid interpretation, courts must identify the principles to guide their interpretations. In Obergefell,
the Court chose protection of the members of a minority group against
the demeaning life the legislative majority would have allowed them, a
life determined by 19th century understandings of marriage.
The process of identifying the parameters for constitutional
interpretation is one of the most important functions of courts and
lawyers. The fact that it is subject to vigorous debate and is likely
to continue to be so is healthy for our democracy.
Judith G. Greenberg
In a recent blog my colleague Lawrence Friedman
noted, “many cases implicating the Constitution do not turn on the
document’s text.” He was writing in the context of Fourth Amendment
jurisprudence, but his observation is equally if not even more true in
the context of foreign affairs and separation of powers. This is an
area where the Court does not frequently tread for many reasons, not the
least of which is that the Court is not keen to involve itself in what
is usually seen as a turf battle between the two political branches.
Nonetheless, this past term the Court did take up a seemingly mundane
case that has potentially significant consequences in the foreign
affairs and national security arenas, areas where the Framers purposely
created vague lines of authority between the President and Congress. Zivotofsky v. Kerry
involved the petition of the Zivotofskys to have the birth of their
child listed on his U.S. passport and consular report as “Jerusalem,
Israel.” However, since 1948, when President Truman recognized Israel,
he and every subsequent U.S. president have never acknowledged any
country’s sovereignty over Jerusalem. Further, the Secretary of State
has instructed State Department employees to record the place of birth
for U.S. citizens born in Jerusalem as “Jerusalem,” with no further
state affiliation.
Enter Congress, which in 2002 passed Section 214 of the Foreign
Relations Authorization Act titled “United States Policy with Respect to
Jerusalem as the Capital of Israel.” As this title suggests, Section
214 directed the Secretary of State to register the place of birth as
Israel on registration of birth documents, certification of nationality,
and passports for any U.S. citizen born in Jerusalem upon the request
of the citizen or the citizen’s legal guardian. Section 214 was clearly
intended to countermand the directives of the executive with respect to
citizens born in Jerusalem.
The Court framed the clear conflict between the President and
Congress in broad terms: 1. Whether the President has the exclusive
power to grant formal recognition to a foreign sovereign? 2. If he has
that power, can Congress command the President and his Secretary of
State to issue a formal statement that contradicts the earlier
recognition? In an opinion by Justice Kennedy the Court answered yes to
the first question and no to the second.
The Court began its analysis by referring to Justice Jackson’s taxonomy in Youngstown Sheet and Tube Co. v. Sawyer,
noting that this is a case where the President’s power is at its
“lowest ebb” because he is acting in direct contravention of Congress,
and thus he can rely solely on the powers the Constitution grants to him
alone. However, the Constitution is silent as to whether or which
branch has exclusive authority to recognize another sovereign. In fact,
the Constitution does not mention the term “recognition” at all.
Unable to rely on the text, Justice Kennedy opts for a structural
and, ultimately, a pragmatic approach to answer these questions. He
notes that the Reception Clause in Article II directs the President to
receive ambassadors and other public ministers. According to Justice
Kennedy, that sounds a lot like recognition authority. Justice Kennedy
goes on to list a number of other foreign affairs powers the
Constitution vests in the President, such as making treaties and
appointing ambassadors and other public ministers. Even though these
treaty-making and appointments powers require senatorial consent, it is
enough for Justice Kennedy that each is dependent on Presidential power.
It is the President who must initiate the process. From this arguably
thin reed, Justice Kennedy concludes that the President has the power
to grant formal recognition to a foreign sovereign.
Justice Kennedy’s pragmatism is in full view as he goes on to address
the second question, whether Congress can command the President and his
Secretary of State to contradict his earlier recognition. Here the
Court answers no; the President’s power is exclusive. This, according
to the Court, is for the simple and obvious reason that the Nation must
speak with one voice on the matter of recognizing a foreign sovereign.
If the President is to be effective in negotiations over a formal
recognition determination, it must be evident that he speaks for the
Nation.
The conservative wing of the Court dissented in Zivotofsky.
In the most scathing criticism, Justice Scalia questions whether the
President’s recognition power is exclusive, but more to the point, he
contends Section 214 has nothing to do with recognition of foreign
sovereigns. Section 214, Justice Scalia argues, performs the much more
prosaic function of allowing citizens some say in what their Government
says about another country’s boarders in citizenship documents. Because
citizenship documents are matters within Congress’s control, Congress
has the authority to direct what those documents say.
It remains to be seen if this case will have longer-term impacts
beyond its rather narrow facts. However, because the Court does not
wade into this area very often, it is likely that courts, advocates, and
commentators will turn to this case in support of various arguments
over presidential and congressional authority. Some particular points
of note are that that in this case the President argued for a much
broader grant of authority. Citing to the 1936 case United States v. Curtiss-Wright,
the Secretary of State contended that the President has exclusive
authority to conduct diplomatic relations along with the “bulk of
foreign-affairs powers.” The Court declined to read Curtiss-Wright
so broadly, suggesting that too oft-cited language from that case that
the President is the “sole organ of the federal government in the field
of international affairs” is dicta.
Also interesting is that a majority of the Court did find express and
exclusive executive power absent any clear language in the
Constitution. The means by which the Court found this power in the
constitutional structure and the Court’s pragmatic view of how a
government must function is likely to provide a road-map for future
foreign affairs and national security cases where the demarcation
between the President’s and Congress’s power is vague.
Finally, in reaching its decision the Court noted that the President
needs exclusive recognition power in order to be effective. If the
Court believes that effectiveness is the touchstone of exclusive
executive authority granted by the Constitution, than Zivotofsky
is truly a blockbuster case and one that the executive will cite for
generations to come in order to maximize its authority. I suspect that
the Court will be forced to clarify and perhaps narrow this rationale in
some future case, but time will tell.
Victor M. Hansen
Students in constitutional law come to learn what seasoned constitutional lawyers know: many cases implicating the Constitution do not turn on the document’s text. Which is not to say the text isn’t important, just that, in certain areas of constitutional law, the doctrinal tests the court has devised to implement textual commands often take precedence over the words themselves. Consider the Fourth Amendment, as demonstrated by the recent decision in Los Angeles v. Patel, involving the scope of protection afforded business records.
The case concerned a challenge to a Los Angeles ordinance that compelled hotel operators to keep records containing specified information provided by guests, and to make these records available to police officers “for inspection” on demand. The law made the failure to make the records available for inspection punishable by up to six months in jail and a $1,000 fine.
Writing for the majority, Justice Sotomayor concluded the law was unconstitutional under the Court’s Fourth Amendment jurisprudence. The Fourth Amendment protects “[t]he right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures,” and states that “no Warrants shall issue, but upon probable cause.” The Court has long interpreted this provision to mean that, absent a warrant based upon probable cause as determined by a neutral decisionmaker, a search will be deemed unreasonable. There is an exception to this rule for administrative searches, such as those contemplated by the Los Angeles law.
For an administrative search to be constitutional, Sotomayor explained, “the subject of the search must be afforded an opportunity to obtain precompliance review before a neutral decisionmaker.” Absent this opportunity, searches under the ordinance potentially could exceed statutory limits or become tools for harassment. An opportunity to obtain such review is a minimal protection—there would be no need for probable cause to search—and, Sotomayor concluded, could be provided without “imposing onerous burdens on those charged with an administrative scheme’s enforcement.” She also noted that searches authorized by the Los Angeles law did not fall within the narrow category that involve closely regulated businesses, in which the government need not afford any opportunity to object to the search.
In dissent, Justice Scalia would have none of it. He argued that “[t]he Court reaches its wrongheaded conclusion not simply by misapplying … precedent, but by mistaking … precedent for the Fourth Amendment itself.” The only constitutional question, in his view, was “whether the challenged search [was] reasonable.” He concluded, “the limited warrantless searches authorized by Los Angeles’s ordinance [were] reasonable under the circumstances” because, in large part, hotels are “closely regulated businesses.”
Scalia’s approach to the Fourth Amendment begs a question: what does it mean for a search to be constitutionally reasonable?
The constitutional text, of course, does not define reasonableness. And so—as noted above—the Court has held a search as reasonable if it is supported by a warrant based upon probable cause. This is the default rule.
But this is not the only way to implement the reasonableness requirement. Professor Tom Clancy has concluded that the Framers likely understood “reasonableness” to require government agents to have a reason to search a particular person or place. (See The Role of Individualized Suspicion in Assessing the Reasonableness of Searches and Seizures, 25 U. MEMPHIS. L. REV. 483 (1995)). This is in contrast to the regime authorized under the Los Angeles ordinance, which permitted law enforcement to search hotel records arbitrarily—and, as the Court noted, as “a pretext to harass business owners.”
We should prefer an approach to reasonableness that will not work to diminish the scope of the Fourth Amendment’s commitment to privacy. An understanding that search regimes need only be reasonable, in a rational-basis way—as suggested in Scalia’s dissenting opinion—eventually will undermine that commitment. For the scope of this kind of reasonableness could be quite elastic—if arbitrary records searches are reasonable in the context of hotels, why not in the context of any business where members of the public may congregate? Or any business, like hotels, that is subject to generally applicable regulations?
At bottom, there is an important difference between viewing a rule as essentially reasonable simply because it serves a legitimate government interest—in Patel, deterring criminals from operating on hotel premises—and viewing it as essentially unreasonable because, regardless of its salutary purpose, it allows police to search indiscriminately. Judges are understandably reluctant to critically review legislative rules under the former approach, while the latter gives them an objective and consistent basis upon which to ensure that the constitutional protection of privacy is not diminished to a point of irrelevance.
Regulation of hotels is important and the deterrence of criminal activity arguably more so. Under the Fourth Amendment, courts should not allow privacy interests—including those of businesses—to be sacrificed in an effort to achieve either.
Lawrence Friedman
Suppose that S, scion of a prominent wealthy family but a bit of a ne’er do well, drunkenly and negligently wrecks his car, causing severe injury to innocent victim, V. V sues and wins a judgment against S, who is the beneficiary of a trust worth millions of dollars. Is V likely to collect on this judgment?
Not against the trust. Although S continues to benefit from the trust, the document that created it contains a “spendthrift clause.” Under the widely adopted Uniform Trust Code (UTC), a few simple words in the trust document numinously protect its corpus from claims of almost all third parties, including tort victims.
Should you be interested in trusts and estates law? Recently, two prominent economists weighed in on a similar query with regard to economics. Ha-Joon Chang’s 2014 book, Economics: The User’s Guide, encouraged his readers to develop some facility with economic questions, the answers to most of which depend on the application of moral values and political views. His point was that when non-economists fail to engage economic questions, we get solutions skewed to the political biases of a handful of economists.
Likewise, French economist Thomas Piketty warned that “the distribution of wealth is too important an issue to be left to economists, sociologists, historians, and philosophers.” Instead, he urged, everyone should be interested and involved. Piketty reported that inherited wealth accounted for at least 50–60% of total private capital in the United States in the late twentieth century and accounts for a much larger share today.
As in economics, moral and political values decide many questions about our laws governing inheritance. And if inheritance stands to play an increasing role in who gets what, as Piketty claims it will, questions of inheritance are crucial in determining how our resources are allocated.
Upton Sinclair wrote that it’s “difficult to get a man to understand something, when his salary depends on his not understanding it.” Contemporary psychological studies confirm that what is now called “motivated reasoning” pervades our decision-making process. Rare is the person who adopts a political perspective or moral view that runs counter to his or her own livelihood. Trusts and estates lawyers make their living helping families hold onto their wealth across generations, meaning they are likely to be biased on questions regarding inheritance. Their vested interest runs towards ensuring entrenchment, rather than disbursement, of wealth. And they have outsized influence on the substance of inheritance law because they are motivated to give it their attention.
Let’s revisit S, the wealthy young man who negligently injured V. After V wins her judgment, Lawyer L defends S’s trust interest against V’s attempt to levy against it, but remains unpaid after billing S many times for his legal work. Fed up, L goes to court and gets a judgment against S for his fees. Is L likely to collect against the assets of the trust? Yes, because while the UTC shields the assets of the trust from almost all creditors’ claims, making it impenetrable by V, it opens the door to “a judgment creditor who has provided services for the protection of a beneficiary’s interest in the trust.” Meanwhile, V remains uncompensated for her injuries.
Kent Schenkel
|
|